The Free Speech Act: The Strongest Speech Protection Ever Legislated
As the third bill of the Great Repeal, our Act would politically entrench the most radical protection of free speech humans have ever known in the Britannic cradle of individual liberty, greater even than the First Amendment.

Free speech is being able to deny the Holocaust, burn the Quran, call your opponents fascist, and publish the adultery of the King. Speech precedes human government, and is beyond its legitimate jurisdiction. Therefore it comes from Nature, and is a prerequisite natural right. As no government possesses the authority to interfere with it, it is a negative right. It is a form of negative liberty: something which ought be absent of obstacles or coercion which prevent individuals from engaging in it as they choose. It is not a permission slip you get from a government.
Speech enables dialogue, which is our only beastial alternative to violence and our chief means of educating our children. It is fundamental to experimental creativity, which is the basis of scientific understanding, artistic beauty, and innovation which drives trade. It is the functional core of error correction, when one's views are fallacious. It provides the means for the enunciation of truth via open debate, dissent, and competition between different viewpoints.
We make no apology whatsoever for the most aggressive and ambitious speech proposal in British and/or Commonwealth times to date. Perhaps, the timid Anglosphere itself, outside of the American tradition. The FSA is so draconian in its declaration of liberty, it barely stops short of demanding capital punishment for those who violate it. The time has come for the home of liberty to make its stand and explain to the modern world it created what freedom and liberty really mean.
Read the draft Free Speech Act in full here (44 pages):
This Act isn't just radical; it's revolutionary and exceptionally aggressive on a scale the British have not been used to for a few hundred years, but quite enjoy. Among its myriad of entrenched clauses, it:
- Explicitly denies the Crown and its ministers free speech;
- Sends politicians and employers to prison for interfering with individual speech;
- Bans censorship entirely, public or private;
- Excludes hardcore pornography as prostitution;
- Abolishes the Public Order Act and every other repulsive UK law;
- Immunises national security whistleblowers;
- Entrenches freedom of speech higher than Parliament's own sovereign authority so deeply it is practically impossible to repeal.
We thank the indefatigable Preston Byrne, who is not only leading the fightback against the nefarious Online Safety (Censorship) Act, but originally drafted one of the best and most elegant First Amendment-style speech laws for the Adam Smith Institute.
Why "The" Freedom Of Speech?
The use of "the" in the First Amendment's phrase "the freedom of speech" represents far more than a grammatical choice: it embodies a fundamental philosophical position about the nature of rights. By employing the definite article, the US Constitution's framers were explicitly acknowledging freedom of speech exists as a pre-political, natural right that predates government itself. The definite article signals this freedom is already understood, established, and inviolable: a concept so fundamental to human nature it requires no governmental definition or creation.
In the American context, this linguistic choice reflected the deep influence of Enlightenment philosophy, particularly John Locke's natural rights theory, on the founding generation. Madison, Jefferson, and their contemporaries operated from the premise certain rights existed in the State of Nature, i.e. inherent to human beings by virtue of their humanity rather than as gifts from rulers or governments. The definite article "the" served as a textual anchor connecting American constitutional law to this broader philosophical tradition, while also drawing upon established legal precedents from English common law and the writings of jurists like William Blackstone. When Madison crafted "the freedom of speech" alongside "the freedom of the press," he was deliberately placing these protections within an existing framework of recognised liberties.
The implications of this word choice extend far beyond historical curiosity into the very heart of constitutional interpretation. If the First Amendment had simply guaranteed "freedom of speech" without the definite article, it might suggest Congress was defining the boundaries and nature of this right for the first time. Instead, "the freedom of speech" implies this liberty has objective content and boundaries which exist independently of governmental decree. This understanding reinforces the idea the Bill of Rights functions not as a list of government-granted privileges, but as a recognition of pre-existing constraints on governmental power—a constitutional acknowledgment certain human freedoms are so fundamental they lie beyond the legitimate reach of political authority to create, modify, or revoke.
The Soviet Invention Of "Hate Speech"
The USSR began the inversion of democracy from rule of the majority to protection of the minority during the drafting of the 1948 United Nations Declaration of Universal Human Rights. The caring Soviets were "concerned" about their former enemies – German National Socialists and Italian Fascists – being afforded the right to espouse talk or group association which they considered "fascist" or "of an antidemocratic nature."
It sounded simple enough.
Freedom of speech and the press should not be used for the purposes of propagating fascism, aggression and for provoking hatred as between nations.
As the Gulag system held 2.2 million people, they countered with a proposal which included an obligation to prohibit:
Any advocacy of national, racial, or religious hostility or of national exclusiveness or hatred and contempt, as well as any action establishing a privilege or a discrimination based on distinctions of race, nationality, or religion constitute a crime and shall be punishable under the law of the state.
British negotiators, who were stalwart at limiting speech rights at the point of incitement to violence only, smelled a rat.
"these words would afford a wider power for the limitation of freedom of publication than is necessary or desirable,” They found “it would be inconsistent for a Bill of Rights whose whole object is to establish human rights and fundamental freedoms to prevent any Government, if it wished to do so, from taking steps against publications whose whole object was to destroy the rights and freedoms which it is the purpose of the Bill to establish.
In other words, this definition of "fascism" would be broadly interpreted to ensure critics of communism (i.e. those showing favour towards capitalism and liberal democracy) could be voluntarily excluded from the USSR's obligation to uphold the declaration.
The British won. Twenty years later, the Western countries lost.
During the 1954 drafting of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, the communist bloc demanded amendments to ban "incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence", which was claimed to derive from the need to criminalise "incitement to hatred", or:
Suppress manifestations of hatred which, even without leading to violence, constituted a degradation of human dignity and a violation of human rights.
The communist bloc didn't relent. Next, within the 1965 International Convention for the Elimination of all Racial Discrimination, all signatories were required to:
Declare an offence punishable by law all dissemination of ideas based on racial superiority or hatred, incitement to racial discrimination.
This led to the Race Relations Act 1965, which gave us today's disastrous Equality Act. As the Institute of Public Affairs rightly concludes:
Writes the Danish human rights advocate Jacob Mchangama, ‘that the increasing emphasis on criminalizing words that wound, offend, or hurt is the brainchild of the very totalitarian states with which Western European states were locked in an ideological battle during the Cold War.’
The human rights movement to restrict hate speech and racial discrimination was an ideological power play by the Communist Bloc that was looking for human rights law to approve the suppression of political dissent. The adoption of hate speech restrictions was not intended to liberate minorities (as so many contemporary human rights advocates claim), but to restrain democrats.
The Poisonous Rise Of Compelled Speech
The classical understanding of free speech focused primarily on negative liberty—the government's prohibition from silencing citizens or preventing the expression of ideas. This framework around what the state could not do to restrict speech. However, contemporary legal and social developments have fundamentally inverted this paradigm, transforming free speech from a shield against governmental interference into a weapon of compelled expression. Modern citizens now face not merely the traditional threat of being silenced, but the more insidious danger of being forced to speak in ways which correspond with state-sanctioned ideologies or social orthodoxies.
Under a slew of current UK legislation, citizens can be compelled to provide encryption keys, passwords, and other digital information under penalty of imprisonment, effectively forcing them to participate in their own investigation. This represents a fundamental breach of the principle against self-incrimination and the natural right to remain silent in the face of state power.
This insanity has even spread to criminalising prayer outside clinics where children are murdered by doctors.
Similarly, the growing demands for ideological conformity through compelled speech, whether mandating the use of personal pronouns, requiring declarations of support for specific social movements, or forcing public affirmations of contested political positions, transforms the state and its allied institutions from protectors of speech into its most dangerous adversaries. These requirements do not merely restrict what citizens may say; they dictate what citizens must say, co-opting their voices for messages they may fundamentally reject.
Online platforms, operating with the tacit approval and often explicit encouragement of government authorities, now function as engines of compelled speech, requiring users to affirm community standards which frequently amount to ideological litmus tests. The internet's permanence and reach mean compelled speech is no longer confined to specific moments or contexts but becomes a persistent requirement for participation in modern society.
Professional advancement, educational opportunities, and social acceptance increasingly depend upon one's willingness to mouth approved formulations and demonstrate proper ideological subservience. This represents a complete inversion of English liberty, where the greatest threat comes from government attempts to silence dissent.
Today's citizens face the arguably more totalitarian prospect of being forced to become unwilling advocates for positions they oppose, their own voices weaponised against their conscience and judgment. The right to remain silent, once considered fundamental to human dignity, has been systematically dismantled in favour of a system which demands not merely compliance, but enthusiastic participation in one's own ideological subjugation.
The Perversion Of Pornography As "Speech"
Denmark became the first nation to legalise hardcore pornography in 1969, followed by the Netherlands in 1971 and West Germany in 1973. The United Kingdom maintained stricter controls through the Obscene Publications Act until the 1990s, when enforcement became increasingly selective and European Union directives regarding free movement of goods created practical limitations on censorship. The European Court of Human Rights gradually recognised sexuality as falling within Article 10 protections, though with broader allowances for state regulation than American jurisprudence permitted.
This has ultimately led to the absurdity of provocateurs like Peter Tatchell attempting to lobby for a "right to sexual expression."
The classification of sexually explicit material as "protected speech" fundamentally altered the relationship between government authority and private expression, establishing precedents which extend far beyond the adult entertainment industry into contemporary debates over digital content and platform regulation.
Prior to the 1950s, American obscenity law operated under the restrictive Hicklin standard, derived from the 1868 English case Regina v. Hicklin. This test prohibited material which could "deprave and corrupt those whose minds are open to such immoral influences," effectively allowing censorship based on the potential impact on the most vulnerable members of society. Under this framework, virtually all sexually explicit material faced legal prohibition, with authorities maintaining broad discretionary power to suppress publications deemed morally corrupting.
The foundational shift occurred in Roth v. United States (1957), where the Supreme Court established obscenity lay outside First Amendment protection while simultaneously raising the threshold for what constituted obscenity. The Court replaced the Hicklin test with a new standard requiring material be "utterly without redeeming social importance" and appeal to "prurient interest" when judged by contemporary community standards. This decision marked the first explicit recognition sexually oriented material could possess constitutional protection, creating a category of "non-obscene" sexual content which enjoyed First Amendment coverage.
The Warren Court continued expanding these protections through a series of decisions in the 1960s. Jacobellis v. Ohio (1964) introduced the requirement that obscene material be "patently offensive," while Memoirs v. Massachusetts (1966) established all three elements of the Roth test must be satisfied simultaneously. These decisions effectively created a constitutional sanctuary for sexually explicit material which possessed any literary, artistic, political, or scientific value, making successful obscenity prosecutions increasingly difficult.
Miller v. California (1973) established the current three-pronged test for obscenity: material must appeal to prurient interest, depict sexual conduct in a patently offensive way, and lack serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. Crucially, Miller allowed local communities to establish their own standards for the first two prongs while maintaining a national standard for the third. This framework effectively legalised hardcore pornography in jurisdictions with permissive communities, particularly California, where the adult entertainment industry subsequently concentrated in San Fernando valley.
The state's courts consistently applied narrow interpretations of obscenity law, while prosecutors demonstrated reluctance to pursue cases against adult entertainment. This regulatory environment proved particularly advantageous following the Supreme Court's decision in California v. Freeman (1988), which effectively legalised hardcore pornographic film production by distinguishing it from prostitution under pandering statutes.
The Freeman decision emerged from prosecutors' attempts to circumvent First Amendment protections by charging adult film producers with pandering, arguing paying performers for sexual acts constituted solicitation for prostitution. However, the California Supreme Court ruled such prosecutions violated constitutional speech protections when applied to legitimate film production for the benefit of third party audiences, inadvertently providing explicit judicial sanction for the commercial production of hardcore pornography.
The Glorious Act: A Guide
The Free Speech Act is drafted as a comprehensive constitutional law which establishes absolute protection for freedom of speech in the United Kingdom. The Act is structured in five main parts, covering foundations, criminal penalties, civil enforcement, legitimate restrictions, and institutional provisions.
Section 1: Interpretation and Definitions
This section establishes detailed definitions for key terms throughout the Act. Notable definitions include:
Speech is defined broadly to encompass any expression, utterance, writing, conduct, or communication through any medium by any person or entity expressing ideas, opinions, beliefs, or information.
Natural right is defined as a pre-political, inherent right that exists before and independent of any government, deriving from human nature as free and rational creatures, which no authority may legitimately restrict.
Censorship means any action intended to suppress, restrict, limit, impede, or interfere with lawful expression of speech.
Compel includes forcing, coercing, mandating, requiring, or pressuring through legal, financial, or social means to express any message against one's will.
The definitions distinguish between public entities (governmental bodies and officials) and private entities (corporations, trusts, charitable organisations, educational establishments, employers, and other non-governmental entities).
Essential services are specifically defined to include banking, payment processing, internet access, hosting, telecommunications, and domain registration services.
Pornography receives a detailed three-part definition covering recorded sexual acts for gratification, artificially generated sexual content, and written sexual descriptions lacking serious value.
Violence is defined as physical force causing damage to property, injury to persons, or interference with lawful activity, explicitly excluding such acts from protected speech.
Safety is narrowly defined as protection from imminent and specific physical threats, explicitly excluding subjective feelings of discomfort or emotional distress.
Section 2: Right to the Freedom of Speech
This section establishes the fundamental principle every person possesses an absolute and inviolable natural right to freedom of speech. The section declares this right has always existed as pre-political, inherent in human nature, and preceding state authority. Importantly, it clarifies this right imposes no positive obligation on any entity to facilitate speech. Speech is not a permission slip you get from the government; it is completely outside the jurisdiction of any government.
The natural right encompasses freedom from interference with expressing opinions, freedom from compelled expression, freedom from interference with receiving and imparting information, and freedom from interference with using any medium for expression.
Section 3: Government Speech Exclusion
This section creates a comprehensive exclusion whereby the Act does not protect speech by government entities when acting in official capacity. The exclusion covers the Crown, all government departments, Ministers of the Crown, devolved administrations, local authorities, and all public sector employees including civil servants, teachers in state schools, NHS employees, police officers, armed forces personnel on duty, and judges when acting judicially.
The exclusion applies to all official communications including speeches, written communications, policy statements, and communications made through official channels or while in uniform. However, these individuals retain full protection for purely personal speech that is clearly unconnected to their official role and not made using official resources.
Upon termination of employment or cessation of official duties, such persons immediately regain full protection. The section ensures government entities cannot claim free speech protections to resist disclosure obligations, parliamentary scrutiny, or public accountability measures. Nor can they use weasel words to claim gender ideology, gratuitous sex "education," or puberty medication forced on children is "free expression."
Section 4: Prohibited Restrictions
This section establishes no public or private entity may engage in censorship, with a specific exception allowing parents to restrict material to children under 18. It prohibits denying service based on lawful speech, discrimination or penalties based on lawful speech, establishing policies which restrict lawful speech beyond specific exceptions, compelling expression contrary to conscience, or engaging in acts which would chill lawful speech.
Service providers and venue operators must take reasonable measures to prevent heckler's vetoes and cannot establish designated areas which limit lawful speech to specific locations.
Public entities are specifically prohibited from providing funding to entities which engage in censorship, delegating speech-related functions to NGOs or third parties, establishing advisory panels to stigmatise lawful speech, or participating in information-sharing forums which facilitate speech suppression. Public officials who authorise such activities face personal liability, and any public money awarded in contravention becomes immediately repayable with a ten-year disqualification from future public funding.
Section 5: Sexual Materials Classification
This section distinguishes between legitimate forms of expression and unprotected material. Educational materials on sexuality, artistic depictions within recognised traditions, and scholarly materials for medical or scientific purposes receive protection.
Pornography as defined in the Act under the Miller Test, obscene material lacking serious value, and digital content subscription services facilitating commercial sexual transactions are excluded from protection. The section amends the Obscene Publications Act 1959 to provide clearer definitions and establishes a defence for material serving legitimate purposes.
Put simply: hardcore pornography is not speech, and it is excluded from any definition of being speech.
Section 6: Prohibition on Ideological Licensing
This section prohibits any entity from requiring endorsement of political, ideological, or moral beliefs as conditions for employment, admission, advancement, licensure, funding, or participation. It specifically bars mandatory statements or declarations expressing support for particular viewpoints and prohibits mandatory training requiring affirmation of contested positions.
Violations result in civil liability, contract voidance, and forfeiture of public funding. The section preserves general professional conduct standards unrelated to belief or conscience.
Section 7: Natural Right Against Compelled Expression
This section establishes comprehensive protection against compelled expression, including explicit compulsion and indirect manipulation through psychological techniques or "nudging." It specifically prohibits using terrorism, national security, or public safety as pretexts to compel British citizens to waive their right against self-incrimination.
The section establishes a broad right to remain silent, providing that no British citizen may be compelled to speak or testify against their will, no adverse inference may be drawn from exercising this right, and evidence obtained through compelled speech is inadmissible. Limited exceptions exist for terrorism investigations with judicial authorisation, immigration proceedings involving non-citizens, and border control operations.
Section 8: Offences by Public Officials
This section actually creates criminal offences for public officials who knowingly restrict freedom of speech. Ministers of the Crown who introduce speech-restricting legislation face up to ten years imprisonment and permanent disqualification from ministerial office. Other public officials face up to seven years imprisonment, fines, and ten-year bans from public office.
The section includes defences for officials who took reasonable compliance steps, acted on legal advice, or reasonably believed their actions prevented imminent threats to life. It prohibits creating any public body with speech restriction purposes and extends liability to advisory, consultancy, academic, or NGO personnel who receive public funding and engage in speech suppression activities.
Section 9: Criminal Offences by Private Entities
Private entities which intentionally violate the prohibited restrictions face fines up to £1,000,000 or 10% of annual worldwide turnover, whichever is greater, plus daily fines of £50,000 for continued violations. Corporate officers who consent to or neglect to prevent violations face up to two years imprisonment.
Defences exist for entities with reasonable compliance systems, genuine technical errors promptly remedied, or court-ordered actions. The section extends liability to privately funded advisors and NGOs engaging in speech suppression.
Section 10: Artificial Intelligence and Synthetic Media
This section treats AI-generated expression as speech of the person who directed the system. It excludes from protection synthetic media which circumvents prohibitions against threats, fraud, or defamation by disguising sources, falsely attributing statements, or creating false impressions of impersonated persons engaging in speech they did not make.
Exceptions exist for clearly marked parody, educational demonstrations, and legally authorised security operations.
Section 11: Criminal Threats and Malicious Communications
This section defines narrowly the criminal forms of speech not protected by the Act. Genuine threats must involve specific intent, reasonable interpretation as credible threats, specific targets, and present capability to carry out the threat.
Malicious targeted communications are limited to persistent harassment continuing after cessation requests, explicit graphic violence intended to intimidate, or obscene communications intended to cause distress. The section also covers indecent exposure serving no legitimate purpose and disclosure of private information intended to facilitate physical harm.
Section 12: Civil Liability of Private Entities
Private entities violating the Act face civil liability including damages, exemplary damages for willful violations, specific performance orders, and requirements to publish public acknowledgments of violations.
Essential services must operate as public accommodations with transparent, viewpoint-neutral terms of service and detailed explanations for service denials with appeal rights. Foreign entities must comply with UK law, facing penalties based on worldwide turnover, business prohibition, and personal liability for directors.
The section places the burden of proof on defendant entities, awards legal costs to successful claimants, and considers resource disparities in assessing damages.
Section 13: Digital Platforms and Services
Digital service providers must maintain viewpoint-neutral policies and refrain from algorithmic suppression. Essential service providers cannot deny service based on lawful speech, discriminate based on viewpoint, or participate in organised campaigns targeting lawful speech.
Section 14: Public Spaces and Venues
This section prohibits designated speech areas which limit where lawful speech may occur. Public forums must be subject to the Act's protections. Venue owners must take reasonable measures to prevent heckler's vetoes, including providing appropriate security, removing disruptive individuals, accommodating opposing viewpoints separately, and not cancelling events due to threats.
The section establishes a fund to assist smaller venues with security measures and prohibits "safe buffer zones" or "safe spaces" except where specific, credible, imminent physical threats exist and restrictions are narrowly tailored.
Section 15: Educational and Professional Settings
Educational institutions cannot deny credentials based on lawful expression, compel ideological affirmations, or establish speech-restricting policies. Employers cannot take adverse action against employees for lawful expression outside work, compel conscience-violating expression, or require ideological training.
Violations result in civil liability, potential funding reductions for educational institutions, and institutional penalties. No governmental entity may restrict educational institutions based on protected speech by their students, faculty, or staff.
Section 16: Legitimate Exceptions to Protected Speech
This section narrowly defines unprotected speech categories - things which are not legitimate speech. True threats require specific intent, reasonable interpretation as credible, specific targets, and present capability. Treason is limited to advocating violent government overthrow, explicit calls for killing British citizens based on nationality, or providing material assistance to enemies during wartime.
Defamation protections are enhanced with strategic lawsuit protections, actual malice requirements for public figures, and public interest defences. Speech integral to criminal conduct must directly facilitate criminal acts where the statute is not aimed at restricting speech.
The section covers fraud, perjury, false allegations causing severe injury, deliberate malicious misrepresentation of political opponents, hardcore pornography involving children, revenge pornography, and direct incitement to violence.
Importantly, the section declares which subjective experiences of offence or emotional distress do not constitute legal injury or harm sufficient to restrict otherwise protected speech.
Section 17: National Security Exceptions
Speech may be temporarily restricted on national security grounds only when necessary to prevent specific, imminent, grave injury, narrowly tailored, with no less restrictive alternative, authorised by court order, and subject to 30-day sunset provisions.
The section provides for post-restriction transparency through Freedom of Information requests after one year, with limited exceptions for active intelligence sources or individual safety. It amends the Official Secrets Act 1989 to create defences for disclosures made to Members of Parliament or High Court judges where public interest outweighs harm to national security.
Section 18: Prohibitions on Information Recategorisation
This section prohibits establishing categorisations of speech that would restrict protected expression, labelling speech in ways that serve as censorship pretexts ("hate speech"), creating speech evaluation systems for allocating resources, or conflating non-speech activities with protected speech for regulatory purposes.
It prohibits reinterpreting Act terms to restrict speech and specifically abolishes "hate speech" as a legal concept, declaring that speech shall not be criminalised for causing offence or emotional distress.
Section 19: Protection for Whistleblowers
Whistleblowers exposing Act violations receive immunity from civil and criminal liability, protection from adverse action, presumption of good faith, and entitlement to compensation for retaliation. Protections apply regardless of confidentiality obligations, security classifications, or disclosure methods. Agreements restricting such whistleblowing are void, and retaliation constitutes a criminal offence.
Section 20: Anti-Circumvention and Prevention Programs
This section prohibits creating laws, policies, or procedures with speech restriction purposes or effects. It specifically bans programs similar to counter-terrorism strategies that monitor speech, belief, or ideology, attempt to identify persons based on expression, or seek to intervene in idea development or expression.
Local authorities lose all speech-related powers. Entities cannot achieve through indirect means what is prohibited directly. Circumvention attempts face criminal liability and expedited court dismissal with costs. Courts must apply heightened scrutiny requiring compelling interest, narrow tailoring, and absence of less restrictive alternatives.
Section 21: Protection Against Foreign Interference
Foreign governments, entities, or individuals attempting to restrict lawful UK speech commit offences, including through extraterritorial laws, establishing UK censorship entities, economic coercion, or technological impediments. UK entities cannot partner with non-compliant foreign entities or implement foreign-directed speech restrictions.
Section 22: Repeals and Schedule
This section repeals numerous existing laws including the Obscene Publications Act 1857, portions of Official Secrets Acts, the Video Recordings Act 1984, Malicious Communications Act 1988, Public Order Acts, sections of Terrorism Acts, Communications Act provisions, the Racial and Religious Hatred Act 2006, the Online Safety Act 2023, and various other speech-restricting legislation.
Section 23: Dissolution of Regulatory Bodies
The Office of Communications (Ofcom) and British Board of Film Classification are dissolved, with all speech regulation functions ceasing. Non-speech regulatory functions may be transferred by statutory instrument.
Section 24: Judicial Review and Remedies
Any person whose speech rights are violated may bring claims, with restricting entities bearing the burden of proof by clear and convincing evidence. Courts must apply strong presumptions against speech restrictions, provide expedited 14-day review for ongoing violations, award appropriate remedies including costs and legal fees to successful claimants.
Frivolous regulatory actions trigger exemplary damages, personal costs, and criminal referrals. Standing is broadly construed, with six-year limitation periods from discovery and no time limits for ongoing violations.
Section 25: Voluntary Waiver for Military and Intelligence Personnel
Military and intelligence personnel may voluntarily waive certain rights during service, but waivers must be freely given, written, specific in scope and duration, revocable with 30 days notice, automatically expiring after five years or service termination, and cannot be employment conditions.
No waiver permits complete rights abrogation, indefinite restrictions, purely private matter restrictions, or prevention of serious wrongdoing disclosure. Personnel retain rights to make protected disclosures to Members of Parliament or High Court judges.
Section 26: Declaratory Relief and Precedential Judgments
Courts may issue declaratory relief identifying invalid speech restrictions, establishing binding precedent, clarifying exception boundaries, and providing interpretation guidance. Declarations bind all UK courts, apply prospectively to similar restrictions, create invalidity presumptions, must be publicly registered, and are binding on all entities.
After declarations, entities have 30 days to cease prohibited practices or face automatic liability. Courts are encouraged to issue broad protective declarations addressing emerging technologies and methods. A public registry provides free access to all declaratory judgments with notification systems.
Section 27: Maximum Constitutional Entrenchment and Supremacy
This section establishes the Act as supreme constitutional law requiring extraordinary procedures for amendment: identical passage in three separate Parliaments after three general elections, 75% supermajorities in both Houses each time, 66% approval by total eligible electorate in referendum, personal Sovereign endorsement based on constitutional judgment, and six months notice to Commonwealth Realms and NATO allies.
The Crown becomes constitutional guardian of free speech rights, with Royal Assent permanently withheld from speech-restricting measures and governments violating the Act deemed to have constructively violated their oath, triggering immediate parliamentary dissolution.
International obligations include bilateral free speech protection treaties with NATO allies and Commonwealth Realms, with treaty partners pledging to sever relations if the Act is weakened, making UK membership conditional on maintaining protections, and creating international law obligations making domestic repeal a treaty breach.
Attempts to repeal trigger automatic constitutional consequences including immediate parliamentary dissolution, suspension of salaries, deficit spending prohibition, constitutional crisis procedures, and personal disqualification from public office.
Citizens retain permanent rights to petition for parliamentary dissolution with 100,000 signatures, withhold taxes from violating governments, exercise civil disobedience with legal immunity, recall Members of Parliament through 10% constituent petition, and form citizen tribunals to investigate violations.
The section establishes constitutional conventions prohibiting speech restrictions in election manifestos, creating Opposition duties to resist speech restrictions, protecting civil servant refusal to implement violations, and requiring enhanced oaths specifically upholding free speech.
Emergency powers cannot suspend the Act, with such attempts constituting constructive treason. International law, European Court decisions, and UN resolutions cannot override the Act. Should the Act be repealed, it declares citizens may invoke emergency constitutional restoration procedures and authorises withdrawal of consent from government to establish alternative arrangements protecting free speech.
The Magna Carta of Speech: A New Constitutional Settlement
This Act represents nothing less than the most profound constitutional revolution in British governance since the Glorious Revolution of 1688. Where the Bill of Rights established parliamentary supremacy over monarchical power, the Free Speech Act establishes the supremacy of individual conscience over all forms of institutional authority. It completes the arc of British constitutional development which began at Runnymede eight centuries ago, where barons forced King John to acknowledge even sovereign power must bow before fundamental rights.
The Act's entrenchment provisions shatter the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty which has defined British constitutionalism for three centuries. Parliament, the ancient guardian of liberty against royal prerogative, now finds itself constitutionally bound by principles which transcend its own authority. This represents the ultimate triumph of natural law over positive law, of eternal principle over temporal power. Its asset would represent the day Britain chose to bind itself irrevocably to the defence of human conscience against every form of tyranny, whether governmental, corporate, or social.
The Iron Fortress of Free Thought
The Act constructs an impregnable constitutional fortress around the human mind. Its definitions are crafted with surgical precision to close every avenue through which authoritarians have historically throttled dissent. The broad definition of speech encompasses not merely spoken words but every form of human expression, while the narrow definition of legitimate exceptions ensures no future government can expand restrictions through creative reinterpretation.
The criminal penalties create a new class of constitutional crime: the violation of natural rights by those entrusted with power. Ministers who introduce speech-restricting legislation face personal imprisonment, marking the first time in British history elected officials bear criminal liability for legislative acts. This transforms the constitutional relationship between rulers and ruled, making clear even democratic majorities cannot legitimately suppress fundamental rights they possess no jurisdiction over.
The civil enforcement mechanisms weaponise the courts in defence of speech rights, creating a presumption any restriction on expression is constitutionally suspect. Private entities which control the essential infrastructure of modern communication find themselves bound by constitutional obligations previously reserved for governments. The algorithmic suppression provisions recognise twenty-first century censorship operates through code rather than law, ensuring technological authoritarianism cannot escape constitutional scrutiny.
The Commonwealth Cascade
The Act's requirement for bilateral free speech protection treaties with Commonwealth Realms and NATO allies are so extreme they create the potential for a constitutional cascade across the Anglosphere. As Britain binds itself to these protections, it invites its closest allies to join in creating an international constitutional order based on absolute speech rights.
Canada, struggling with human rights tribunals which prosecute comedians for jokes, faces a stark choice: embrace these protections or see its relationship with Britain fundamentally altered. Australia, with its expanding online censorship apparatus, must decide whether to join this constitutional revolution or find itself increasingly isolated from its traditional allies. New Zealand's hate speech laws place it on a collision course with these new international obligations.
The Act creates the possibility of a new constitutional Commonwealth, bound not by shared history but by shared commitment to the fundamental right of human expression. It represents the evolution of the Westminster system to a metaphysical concept with speech rights as its limiting principle.
The Economic Architecture of Freedom
The Act's treatment of essential services as public accommodations revolutionises the relationship between commerce and constitutional rights. Banking, payment processing, internet hosting, and telecommunications services become constitutionally bound to serve all lawful speakers without discrimination. This breaks the corporate chokehold on dissent which has characterised the early twenty-first century, where private companies exercise more effective censorship power than governments ever possessed.
The global scope of enforcement, with penalties calculated on worldwide turnover (as the Online Safety Act does), ensures no multinational corporation operating under UK jurisdiction can escape these obligations by claiming foreign incorporation. The personal liability provisions for directors and officers make corporate censorship a personal risk for those who authorise it, transforming the incentive structure which has enabled systematic suppression of lawful speech.
The prohibition on government funding for censorious entities starves the apparatus of institutional censorship, cutting off the financial lifeblood of the NGOs, think tanks, and academic centres which have constructed the intellectual framework for modern speech restrictions. No longer can governments fund private entities to accomplish indirectly what they are forbidden to do directly.
The Death of Soft Tyranny
The Act's prohibition on compelled expression strikes at the heart of what Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn called "the lie we must tell." The ideological licensing provisions ensure no person can be forced to affirm beliefs which violate their conscience as a condition of employment, education, or participation in public life. This breaks the backbone of soft totalitarianism, which operates not through physical coercion but through the requirement citizens publicly affirm the regime's ideology.
The enhanced right to remain silent, extending beyond criminal proceedings to all forms of compelled testimony, recognises the modern state's greatest weapon is not the gun but the microphone held to unwilling lips. By constitutionally protecting silence, the Act acknowledges freedom of speech necessarily includes freedom from speech.
The algorithmic suppression provisions recognise modern censorship operates through manipulation of information flows rather than direct prohibition. By requiring transparency in content moderation and prohibiting viewpoint discrimination in algorithmic distribution, the Act prevents the emergence of a two-tier information system where dissenting voices are not silenced but simply rendered invisible.
The Global Counter-Revolution
This Act positions Britain as the leader of a global counter-revolution against the emerging international censorship regime. As supranational organisations, foreign governments, and multinational corporations construct increasingly sophisticated mechanisms for suppressing dissent, Britain declares its constitutional independence from this new international order.
The prohibition on government participation in international information-sharing forums which facilitate speech suppression breaks Britain's participation in the global censorship apparatus. The protection against foreign interference provisions recognise threats to free speech increasingly come not from domestic governments but from foreign powers and international organisations seeking to export their speech restrictions.
The Act's supremacy over international law marks Britain's constitutional exodus from the post-war international legal order which has increasingly prioritised collective rights over individual liberty. This represents a return to the Westphalian principle of national sovereignty, but with a crucial innovation: sovereignty exercised in defence of individual natural rights rather than state power.
The Technological Fortress
The artificial intelligence provisions ensure the Act remains relevant as human communication increasingly involves algorithmic mediation. By treating AI-generated content as the speech of those who direct it, the Act prevents the emergence of a parallel communication system outside constitutional protection. The synthetic media provisions recognise deepfake technology threatens to make truth itself contested, requiring legal frameworks which can distinguish between legitimate expression and technological manipulation.
The digital platform provisions transform major technology companies from private actors exercising discretionary content policies into public utilities bound by constitutional obligations. This represents perhaps the most significant expansion of constitutional rights into the private sphere in modern history, acknowledging that democratic discourse increasingly occurs on privately owned digital platforms.
The Educational Reformation
The prohibition on ideological licensing in educational settings promises to restore intellectual diversity to British universities, which have become increasingly ideologically uniform. By preventing the requirement of diversity statements, loyalty oaths to particular ideologies, and mandatory training in contested political positions, the Act ensures academic careers cannot be made contingent on ideological conformity.
The protection of student speech from institutional retaliation creates a new generation of citizens educated in an environment where dissent is not merely tolerated but constitutionally protected. This reverses decades of increasing campus censorship and promises to produce graduates capable of independent thought rather than ideological conformity.
The Constitutional Moment
This Act represents Britain's constitutional moment of choice between competing visions of human nature and social organisation. It chooses the vision of humans as rational creatures capable of self-government through free discourse over the vision of humans as vulnerable beings requiring protection from harmful ideas. It chooses the robust democracy of open debate over the managed democracy of expert guidance. It chooses the Englishman's liberty over the administrative state.
The extraordinary entrenchment provisions demonstrate the drafters' recognition that constitutional rights mean nothing without constitutional protection against their erosion. By requiring impossible supermajorities, referenda, and international consultation for amendment, the Act acknowledges future generations may be tempted to trade liberty for security, prosperity, or social harmony. The entrenchment provisions are a constitutional message from the present to the future: these rights are not ours to surrender.
The ultimate constitutional safeguard, declaring the uncodified ancient English right of revolution in defence of free speech, marks the Act's recognition constitutions are only as strong as the people willing to defend them. By explicitly authorising resistance to speech restrictions and declaring such resistance a constitutional duty, the Act transforms every citizen into a constitutional guardian.
Leadership of the Anglosphere
This Act positions Britain to lead the Anglosphere into a new constitutional age. The common law tradition which Britain gifted to America, Canada, Australia, and New Zealand created the intellectual foundation for modern constitutional government. This Act represents the next evolution of that tradition, moving from constitutional government limited by rights to constitutional government defined by rights.
The bilateral treaty requirements create the framework for a new kind of international order, based not on shared economic interests or security concerns but on shared constitutional principles. This promises to forge stronger bonds between the democracies of the Anglosphere than any traditional alliance, creating a community of nations united by their commitment to the fundamental dignity of human conscience.
The Act's global enforcement provisions, treating foreign interference with speech rights as a form of aggression, recognise the twenty-first century struggle for freedom is fundamentally a struggle for the right to think and speak freely. By constitutionally committing to defend this right against all threats, foreign and domestic, Britain declares itself the leader of the free world in the most literal sense.
This is Britain's gift to human civilisation: the recognition freedom of speech is intrinsically coupled to prosperity and not merely a political right but a natural right, not merely a legal protection but a constitutional obligation, not merely a national value but a universal principle. In an age when democracies worldwide are restricting speech in the name of safety, security, and social harmony, Britain chooses to bind itself irrevocably to the defence of human expression in all its forms.
The Free Speech Act represents the constitutional culmination of the British genius for liberty. It stands as Britain's definitive answer to the question which has haunted democratic societies since their inception: how free should free people be? The answer, roared by the Lion with characteristic British understatement but revolutionary force, is simply this: completely.