The Turing Test For Migrants
Many people in Britain hold onto the pretence everyone can be reprogrammed as British. Mathematician and codebreaker, Alan Turing, established a test for the imitation of human, civilised behaviour from machines. If it were true, passing the Turing Test should be easy for new entrants, surely?

In 1950, the British mathematician and codebreaker Alan Turing published a seminal paper titled Computing Machinery and Intelligence in the journal Mind. Amid the post-war rise of electronic computation, Turing sidestepped metaphysical questions about consciousness or soul, and instead posed a pragmatic challenge: can machines imitate human behaviour so convincingly their artificiality becomes undetectable? Thus emerged the "imitation game," now known as the Turing Test.
The interrogator, unable to see their subjects, converses via text with both a machine and a human, trying to determine which is which. If the machine can pass for human through language alone, it is deemed to have passed.
Turing's framing was rooted in wartime work and philosophical influences ranging from Descartes to Gödel. He shifted the question from what a mind is to what a mind does. Over time, the Turing Test became a benchmark for artificial intelligence and the inspiration for competitions like the Loebner Prize. It also provoked critiques, such as John Searle's "Chinese Room," which argued syntax is not semantics, or imitation does not imply comprehension.
Today, the test remains provocatively relevant. Generative language models like GPT and Grok pass informal versions of it routinely, simulating empathy, wit, and reflection. But the more convincingly they perform, the more they expose our readiness to accept appearance over essence.
The Turing Test, in 2025, is no longer about machines proving their humanity. It's about humanity lowering the bar for what it means to be human.
This mirrors a broader tension. British immigration policy, through the British Immigration, Nationality, and Citizenship Act (BINCA), offers a contemporary analogue. Part 5 of BINCA introduces a National Integrity Assessment—an algorithmic test for determining whether a non-Englishman can perform Englishness sufficiently to retain or gain conditional citizenship. It is, unmistakably, a civic Turing Test. But unlike the original, which raised questions about authenticity, BINCA represents an urgent compromise.
For in the face of accelerating demographic shifts (where, according to the Office for National Statistics, over 50% of London residents under 18 are of non-White background) the danger is no longer simply dilution but denial.
A growing segment of reactionary thought threatens to spiral into racial purism: the belief no outsider, however loyal or useful, could ever belong in Britain. This is an overcorrection born of real grievance. An understandable, if misguided, response to state-managed ethnic displacement. Yet it is also an intellectual dead end.
BINCA, with all its bureaucracy and abstraction, is not a betrayal of Englishness. It is its last civic defence. It asserts while Englishness cannot be manufactured, it can be approximated—and this approximation, however imperfect, is preferable to ideological purging. It creates a system in which belonging is earned, not presumed—but also not permanently denied.
BINCA As Imitation Game
Part 5 of BINCA sets forth a two-stage system for evaluating Inherited Conditional British Citizens (ICBCs) and British Subjects. The assessment draws on data from HMRC, DWP, local councils, and police databases, producing four key indicators:
- Net tax contribution (T)
- Labour dependency ratio (L_r)
- Assimilation score (A), and
- Conviction class (C).
Stage A functions as an eligibility filter. Applicants must be free from serious criminality, welfare dependency, immigration violations, language deficits, and "cultural-welfare breaches."
This is the first pass of the civic Turing Test—a weeding-out of those whose behaviour fails even the basic pretense of belonging.
Stage B assigns a composite score:
S = (2 × Tk) + (5 × A) + (2 × H) + (2 × N) − (10 × Lr) − (6 × C)
Here, (Tk) is a capped net tax metric, (A) includes civic performance acts (e.g. community service, continuous employment, CEFR B2+ language), (H) and (N) reflect stable housing and neighbourhood ties, and penalties (Lr) are applied for dependency and criminality.
An (S < 0) score leads to immediate revocation. Scores between 0 and 14 trigger a discretionary panel review. Only (S >= 15) maintains status unchallenged.
This system is not a subversion of national identity. It is a codification of civic realism. Like the Turing Test, it does not ask whether one is English, but whether one can act English convincingly enough to be useful to the nation. The analogy is precise: the machine which imitates humanity gains admittance to dialogue; the immigrant who imitates civic Englishness gains conditional trust.
And crucially, it holds a line. It says: not everyone qualifies. But it also says: not everyone must be excluded. It offers a benchmark rooted in contribution and character rather than race or rhetoric.
The Englishman Cannot Be Made
There is no escaping the biological truth: the Englishman is born, not built. He emerges from a lineage, a soil, a memory. No algorithm can write him into being. No certificate can grant what centuries of rootedness have formed.
Yet that truth need not be weaponised into nihilism. Civic nationalism, rightly calibrated, does not deny the primacy of ancestry. It admits while ancestry and jus sanguinis defines the nation, behaviour defines the citizen. BINCA operates within this worldview and perspective. It allows the outsider may never be one of us fully, but may serve, support, and live among us honourably.
This is not betrayal, it is discernment. It is the recognition imitation, though never a substitute, can be a safeguard—a buffer against displacement, and an alternative to ideological dysfunction. It refuses to let the perfect become the enemy of the defensible.
In the absence of such systems, purity spirals emerge—the belief only total homogeneity can ensure continuity. But purity, unchecked, produces sterility. A nation becomes a museum piece, not a living culture. BINCA, in contrast, offers a living filter: harsh, yes, but fair.
Performance With Purpose
BINCA does not call for soul-deep transformation. It demands surface consistency, statistical contribution, and civic visibility. It is not poetic, but functional. And that is enough.
Critics might call it soulless bureaucracy, but they miss the point. In an age where national identity is assaulted by global capital, ideological conformity, and demographic manipulation, it is not romance we need, but structure.
BINCA delivers structure: it defines thresholds; it tracks outcomes; it enforces standards. Most importantly, it refuses to lower those standards to the mere fact of human existence.
It says: we owe something to our hosts. We demand something of our guests.
A Way Of Rejecting Extremes
The Turing Test asked whether imitation could fool us. BINCA asks whether imitation can serve us. It does not pretend simulation equals substance. But it insists in an era of managed decline, measured imitation is better than surrender.
To reject BINCA is to invite the extremes: either total dilution under multicultural sentimentality, or total exclusion under racial absolutism. Neither protects the English. One dissolves them; the other isolates them. BINCA, flawed and bureaucratic, does something better: it filters.
Yes, the Englishman cannot be made. But he can be preserved, by drawing clear lines between those who mimic in good faith and those who do not. BINCA holds that line.
In a nation where fewer and fewer can say, with ancestral certainty, who they are or where they belong, that line is the last thing standing between memory and erasure. Let it hold.